What Is This?
Stuart W. Mirsky
Kirby Urner
Join Us!
Help

Stuart W. Mirsky (Stuart W. Mirsky is the principal author of this blog).
Last 10 Entries:

Sean Wilson's Blog:


Ludwig Wittgenstein:

 For me, Scalia was a terrible judge. And he was terrible because his decisions relied upon intellectual behaviors that were dominant in history at least one century prior to his time on the bench. He used an a-priori format, syllogistic reasoning, formalism, and took positions about ...
... pretty good stuff here. http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2013/03/03/was-wittgenstein-right/?_r=1 But here is my only complaint. Characterizing Wittgenstein's negative attitudes about the field of philosophy, Horwich writes: " There are no startling discoveries to be made ... 'from the armchair' through some blend of intuition, pure reason and ...
... open access special edition published. Looks promising. Anna Boncompagni is one of the authors.
This looks interesting. The way they have framed the issue looks very good. The question is whether the idea of connoisseurship will even enter the picture at all (as it should). The book I am working on now will expand upon this idea. Why do I ...
I am seeking feedback on the enclosed proposal. I wonder if people think it looks like a viable project? Would the thesis of such a book interest you? Basically, the book is a bit personal: it's based upon an intellectual transformation that I went through and ...
... new set of lectures was posted today. It's on Wittgenstein and Philosophy. Will have the final set of lectures, called Wittgenstein on Intelligence, up tomorrow (hopefully). Moore & His Hands Form of Life False Problems Example: Free Will Senses of Knowledge On Definitions Gettier & Banality Alternative Lexicons On ...
... a lecture containing Wittgensteinian approaches to language. Specifically covers precision-talking, names, jargon, family resemblance, senses of talking -- you name it, it's there. http://ludwig.squarespace.com/cond6/
In this lecture, we see Wittgenstein shed the Tractarian orientation and adopt something that he would later call "the new thinking." http://ludwig.squarespace.com/cond5/
Your browser does not support the video tag.
Italian economist Piero Sraffa is credited with causing Wittgenstein to adopt an "anthropological perspective" toward language. One of conversations between the two involved Sraffa's using a "Neapolitan gesture." This video shows how gestures of this sort lack a picture-reality correspondence, which caused Wittgenstein to abandon the ...
Not enough attention is given to Wittgenstein shunning his immense inheritance. What is interesting is that he did this as a young man and showed no indication throughout life to have ever regretted it. It would be one thing to see someone in their later years ...
... new lecture uploaded on Wittgenstein in transition. Has some clips from A.J. Ayer on Logical Positivism. But, overall, nothing too special here: just a hand-waiving lecture. http://ludwig.squarespace.com/cond4/2014/2/20/01-logical-positivism.html
Wittgenstein's example of philosophical scholarship shews an arrogant and radical ideology hiding inside. Wittgenstein wasn't a worker bee slaving for a literature community. He wasn't a member of the "club." He understood that a "company man" could never be a great thinker. Today, however, the academy ...
... just finished putting my newest version of the Tractatus lecture online. Some audio clips are old, however, because my batteries died in the middle of one session. Still, it is pieced together (reconstructed) accurately. http://ludwig.squarespace.com/cond3/2014/1/29/01-the-genesis-of.html
"The world is the totality of facts, not of things," Wittgenstein proclaims in the Tractatus. In this video, this idea is explained. Specifically, the idea of a thought being a picture of a possible state of affairs, for which the proposition claims to be true or ...
There is an old thread on this subject which has been revived on Duncan Richter's blog. You might want to have a look: http://languagegoesonholiday.blogspot.com/2012/11/did-wittgenstein-believe-in-god.html
I've never seen this before. I wonder if anyone can comment on when it was taken? Or the circumstances? He sort of reminds me of Elvis in this one. Click the picture to see where it came from.
A lecture that looks at Bertrand Russell, the analytic movement that he and Gottlob Frege nurtured, and the role that early Ludwig Wittgenstein played. The lecture takes us from Wittgenstein's first year at Cambridge, when he was captured by Russell's analytic patriotism, through to his departure ...
http://www.theatlantic.com/education/archive/2013/11/the-stereotypes-about-math-that-hold-americans-back/281303/ ... article seems to support the idea that traditional and formalistic approaches to mathematics were themselves an unnecessary dressing. If true, an interesting idea: one that has resonance with the notion that meaning is more important than analysis and that "getting it" is something different ...
(sent to analytic re: whether misplaying in a "language game" is a matter of breaching an implied customary rule for communication. Here's the quick answer: the idea is too anthropologic and needs something ideational) ... I am so happy you brought this up. Because this is exactly what ...
    
Search Archives:
Every Entry
Categories
Tags

Duncan Richter's Blog:

The review is here. Thankfully, even though it does mention me, it doesn't say anything bad about my contribution. (Perhaps tactfully, it says almost nothing at all about it.) Here's a taste of the review: This volume is a valuable addition to this growing literature, with a lucid ...
These are all just coincidences, I suppose, but there are some striking similarities between some of Wittgenstein's acts and ideas and elements of War and Peace. Here are three. The Tractatus contains seven main propositions, which are to be overcome in order to see the ...
One of my favorite authors on why fiction is not a distraction from reality. Here's a taste: The night time dream is chaotic and can be genuinely frightening. The dream we call life is filled with joy and suffering, but for many people a lot more ...
It seems paradoxical to write the question, "Does writing exist?" but what I mean is: is there some thing called writing that someone can be good or bad at, teach, or simply do? According to John Warner, we know how to teach writing. But what is ...
This Guardian essay on neoliberalism is frustrating in some ways (too cloudy at key points, and too prone to ad hominem insults), but it's interesting, and brings out the importance of Friedrich von Hayek, whose work probably ought to be engaged with more just because it ...
Moving to this country was the the first time I ever flew in a plane. I landed in Charlottesville, where I lived for five years. I still live just over an hour's drive from there, and go there quite often to eat a meal, do some ...
This looks interesting, in terms of both content and the decision to publish free and online. The title is Pictorial Truth: Essays on Wittgenstein, Realism, and Conservatism, and it's by Kristóf Nyíri. He writes: I am really curious how the scholarly world will react e.g. to ...
My friend Chris Gavaler has co-written a piece with Nathaniel Goldberg on Trump and bullshit for Philosophy Now. If you're interested in this subject then, obviously, you might want to read it. Their conclusion is that a sample of Trump's speech is "beyond bullshit." Here's ...
I talked a bit about Stephen Mulhall's The Great Riddle here and here. This is the last post I intend to write about it, and it's about the part of the book I like the most. Near the end, Mulhall refers to "the sheer wild particularity ...
[What follows is little more than a bunch of quotes strung together. But they are good quotes.] The desirability of seeing what is under our noses and thereby becoming free is a bit of a theme in 19th century European thought. Here's Father ...
Perhaps this isn't worth a blog post, but it's not as if I've been posting much otherwise. Sometimes it's better to have low standards. So here goes. Two things strike me as not just true but obviously true about any increase in the legal minimum ...
This paper needs quite a bit of work, but for anyone interested here is an only very slightly (so far) revised version of the paper I presented at the conference on Peter Winch last weekend in London.
If you're interested in Peter Winch on understanding others, you might be interested in this documentary. Perhaps it's well known, but I only just found it: And here's one on Evans-Pritchard: I haven't watched either one yet, so can't guarantee their quality.
A new issue (Vol 6 No 1 (2017)) is available here.
Some questions that you might want to ask Stephen Mulhall when you read his new book: if talk about God is nonsense, why bother?if talk about God has a use, mustn't it thereby have a meaning after all?if you accept that nonsense is nonsense, that there ...
Just in case anyone's interested, I've revised this paper. The new version is here.
Are there any bad ones? These are the best, and only, three I know: "Woody Allen" by Allo Darlin', "What's Yr Take on Cassavetes" by Le Tigre, and "Roman P" by Psychic TV. The videos aren't very exciting, but the performances are ...
This site looks great. It is designed to be a teaching resource for people who teach philosophy but want to diverge from the usual texts and topics taught. So if you want to teach some Asian philosophy, for instance, this site will (it is not yet complete) ...
I'm enjoying Stephen Mulhall's The Great Riddle very much. Here he is on religious language: ...insofar as God is the source of all that is, possessing in his being all the perfections he causes, then everything in creation is a potential source of imagery for the ...
Matthew Yglesias has an interesting essay on Trump and bullshit at Vox, but I think he goes too far in his attempt to explain what's going on. Here's an example: When Trump says something like he’s just learned that Barack Obama ordered his phones wiretapped, he’s ...
« The Problem with Properties | Main | Moral Judgment, Factual Belief and Wittgenstein's "On Certainty" »
8:11AM

A Jamesian Wittgenstein?

A former professor of mine, Haim Marantz, sent me a paper of his on Richard Rorty and another on John Dewey recently for some comments. I have never been much for American Pragmatism, not since, as an undergraduate, I read a bit of William James and John Dewey and thought them somewhat soft as thinkers. I also concluded, probably because of the way an instructor at the time presented the two, that American Pragmatism really amounted to an argument that the truth is just whatever works and that's the whole story. This just seemed superficial and wrong to me and I gravitated, instead, to what seemed the more rigorous Analytic tradition in England. Later, I discovered Wittgenstein and his approach opened things up for me in a way that made analytic philosophy seem rather limited, too. I learned, eventually, that Wittgenstein was not well read in philosophy however, although he apparently liked Schopenhauer (at least in his youth) and, at some point in his career, had read William James. That surprised me because it seemed to me that there was a huge gap between James' seemingly superficial pragmatic vision of philosophy and Wittgenstein's penetrating understanding of how language shapes and reflects the way we understand things. Yet, years later I discovered that more and more thinkers were finding in Wittgenstein a pragmatic strain linking him firmly to the work of people like James, especially in light of his almost off-hand remark about 'meaning as use' (Philosophical Investigations). This approach forms the basis for understanding semantics in pragmatic terms, an approach to meaning in language that has taken hold in later Anglo-American philosophical thought. Marantz' papers reminded me of all this and were suggestive, as well, in their treatment of Rorty and Dewey.

A number of modern thinkers, Robert Brandom among them, have argued that Wittgenstein in fact stands in a long tradition of pragmatists going back at least as far as Kant and coming up through Hegel to the classic American Pragmatists (Peirce, James and Dewey) and flowering in the efforts of Wittgenstein and Heidegger (no less!) to find a modern voice in the work of people like the American philosophers Wilfrid Sellars and Richard Rorty. Pragmatism was back -- indeed if Brandom is right, it never left us. Only some, like me, had failed to notice. A year ago I picked up a book in a used book store by William James. Two books actually in one volume: Pragmatism and The Meaning of Truth. This volume, with an introduction by A.J. Ayer, consolidates two sets of lectures delivered by James, the first set in Boston as the Lowell Lectures in 1906 and later at Columbia University (with some slight changes according to Ayer) in 1907. The first set was published in 1907 as Pragmatism. The text of that work forms the first part of the volume I bought, which I finally started reading just a few weeks ago. To my surprise, it contains elements which anticipate and predate Wittgenstein's influential On Certainty. In fact, some of the similarities are astounding.

Writing in the chapter titled Pragmatism's Conception of Truth, James affects to describe how we know things to be the case. He makes the point that knowledge is not strictly what we have evidence for but what fits within a system of things we believe and which touch ground only here and there in instances of empirical verification. Knowledge, he says, involves statements we take to be the case because they work within the larger system of beliefs (all those knowledge claims we are prone to make) in a way that does not disrupt that larger system and which may add to it. In the adding there may be changes made, of course, but it's the overall system of interlocking thoughts (beliefs about things) which is at issue in every instance of knowledge we acquire or think we possess.

Verification matters (as Ayer reminds us in the introduction) but it is not on verification in some isolated sense that our knowledge rests but on the overall effectiveness of the system of ideas we learn from those around us -- who have that particular system, for their part, from those who came before them -- and to which we add as we go through our own lives, all of which combine to form the framework of thoughts we hold at any given moment. The truth of any single claim or belief that we hold, of any statement we make, is determined, per James, by its capacity to add to and/or detract as little as possible from the system of interlocking ideas we already possess. That system, on this Jamesian view is constantly put to the test and it is the system, not the individual statements within it, that must stand up to empirical verification.

James' critics (among whom I, in my naivete, was no doubt one, though of no significance for his actual reputation, of course!) took him to mean by this that the particular verification of any statement of belief is irrelevant because all hinges on what the user of the statements wants out of his or her life and so what he or she wants to believe. Truth is what works, on this somewhat simplistic interpretation, i.e., what becomes truth for us is whatever we want it to be because it satisfies our needs of the moment -- and so the possibility of independent truth, of facts that compel us (because that's just how things are) rather than the other way round, is denied. But that wasn't James' view, it turns out, at all. In fact, he argued that the real world invariably compels us, but that the truth claims we make are not simply a function of that compulsion qua immediate empirical feedback but, rather, of overall systemic success -- where success is constituted by the capacity of our entire body of beliefs (or relevant portions thereof) to advance our interests as users of that body of beliefs. The extent to which any particular belief we happen to hold, or arrive at, fits the proximate instance of experience we undergo (and which may prompt us to that belief) is then determined by the ability of that belief to operate successfully within our overall belief system, either to reinforce its efficacy or change it in a way that makes it more efficacious still (or at least does not make it less so). This set of relations between each new statement of belief and those which precede it, and into which it is obliged to fit, governs the truth value we assign to the new belief.

On the Jamesian view, truth is what we ascribe to statements (and to the beliefs they embody). It's not something in the world to be known, not something that somehow underlies the world we experience (as the transcendental rationalists of his era, and against whom he argued, held). Truth, he thought, is valuational (normative, as Brandom would later put it), the truth of any statement being determined by that statement's capacity to support the body of all the other beliefs we hold in a way that sustains their effectiveness (by disrupting them as little as possible or by introducing changes to them which enhance their effectiveness for the entity holding them). This view is far more sophisticated than I had once given James and the other pragmatists credit for. But that only shows my own naivete I suppose. Even more interesting, it turns out, is that James in these lectures actually presaged Wittgenstein's own insights in the latter's On Certainty, sometimes in an eerily familiar way.

James wrote in his sixth lecture in that series (Pragmatism's Conception of Truth, p.99):

Just as we assume Japan to exist without ever having been there, because it works to do so, everything we know conspiring with the belief, and nothing interfering, so we assume that thing to be a clock [here he refers to a clock on the wall in the lecture hall in which he is speaking]. We use it as a clock, regulating the length of our lecture by it. The verification of the assumption here means its leading to no frustration or contradiction. Verifiability of wheels and weights and pendulum is as good as verification. For one truth-process completed there are a million in our lives that function in this state of nascency. They turn us towards direct verification; lead us into the surroundings of the objects they envisage; and then, if everything runs on harmoniously, we are so sure that verification is possible that we omit it, and are usually justified by all that happens.

Though he could not see the inner workings of that clock on the wall he reminded his audience that he was justified in taking it to be what it appeared to be, a clock, and not merely an artifact with certain external appearances, and so to rely on its readings as he gauged the time remaining in his lecture. As Wittgenstein spoke later of knowledge of things in other places which we cannot see but take on faith, holding these, as if naively (i.e., without observational warrant), to be known with certainty, so James speaks here of the existence of Japan and the innards of a clock in just the same way. For James, as for the later Wittgenstein, being certain of something is not merely a function of having evidence to hand. It's much deeper and more complicated.

This Jamesian pragmatism presumes that the world in which we operate is constituted as much by the ideas and beliefs we hold about it as by the sensible phenomena which, as he puts it, "coerce" us. The knowledge we profess to have about it is as much a function of how we approach and make use of the world of sense as of how it reflects those particular sensory phenomena in a representational way. Contrary to the Tractarian Wittgenstein's picture theory of language, James offers a picture of a dynamic system of thoughts about the world (beliefs) which we build up and which informs our discourse, which is, in fact, embodied in our discourse and so shapes what we see around us -- as surely as that which we see shapes us by "coercion."

"Agreement" between the sensory features of our world and our beliefs about them is not, on this view, the building blocks of our knowledge but its ground -- new information arising only in contact with the world of the senses, here and there, when verifiability (the potential to verify) becomes, as James puts it, actual verification (realized instances of verifying) which only occurs piecemeal in our lives, when our system of beliefs touch ground. Most of our knowledge, including those pre-existing beliefs which govern, by selection, what new knowledge we may acquire, is embodied, for James, in what we have learned as we come of age within the cultural milieu in which we happen to stand. But that body of knowledge is dynamic. It's ever growing and ever changing with each new instance of contact with the phenomenal world.

All of this pre-dates the later Wittgenstein of the Philosophical Investigations and On Certainty, when his shift from the picture theory of language in the Tractatus to the idea that language constitutes the world we know in its rules and the uses they govern becomes paramount. James got there first, more than half a century earlier in fact, and Wittgenstein's having read James must suggest his debt to the earlier thinker. If Wittgenstein's emphasis on the place and role of language in philosophical discourse was innovative in its way, and eye opening, James was already touching on the same phenomena as far back as 1907 and earlier.

References (1)

References allow you to track sources for this article, as well as articles that were written in response to this article.

Reader Comments

There are no comments for this journal entry. To create a new comment, use the form below.

PostPost a New Comment

Enter your information below to add a new comment.

My response is on my own website »
Author Email (optional):
Author URL (optional):
Post:
 
Some HTML allowed: <a href="" title=""> <abbr title=""> <acronym title=""> <b> <blockquote cite=""> <code> <em> <i> <strike> <strong>